Subject: Scepticism 18th century (fwd)
Most 18th-century thinkers gave up the quest for metaphysical knowledge
after imbibing Bayle's arguments.
George Berkeley, an Empiricist and Idealist, fought Skeptical doubts by
identifying appearance and reality
and offering a spiritualistic metaphysics. He was immediately seen as
just another Skeptic since he was denying
the world beyond experience.
Bayle's chief 18th-century successor was David Hume. Combining empirical
and skeptical arguments, Hume
charged that neither inductive nor deductive evidence could establish the
truth of any matter of fact. Knowledge
could only consist of intuitively obvious matters or demonstrable
relations of ideas but not of anything beyond
experience; the mind can discover no necessary connections within
experience nor any root causes of experience.
Beliefs about the world are based not upon reason or evidence nor even
upon appeal to the uniformity of nature
but only on habit and custom. Beliefs cannot be justified. Belief that
there is an external world, a self, a God is
common; but there is no adequate evidence for it. Although it is natural
to hold these convictions, they are
inconsistent and epistemologically dubious. "Philosophy would render us
entirely Pyrrhonian, were not Nature
too strong for it." The beliefs that a man is forced to hold enable him
to describe the world scientifically, but
when he tries to justify them he is led to complete Skepticism. Before he
goes mad with doubts, however, Nature
brings him back to common sense, to unjustifiable beliefs. Hume's fideism
was a natural rather than a religious
one; it is only animal faith that provides relief from complete doubt.
The religious context of Skepticism from
Montaigne to Bayle had been removed, and man was left with only his
natural beliefs, which might be
meaningless or valueless.
The central themes in Hume's Skeptical analysis--the basis of induction
and causality, knowledge of the external
world and the self, proofs of the existence of God--became the key issues
of later philosophy. Hume's
contemporary Thomas Reid hoped to rebut Hume's Skepticism by exposing it
as the logical conclusion of
the basic assumptions of modern philosophy from Descartes onward. Such
disastrous assumptions should be
abandoned for commonsensical principles that have to be believed. As Hume
and Kant saw, Reid had not
answered Hume's Skepticism but had only sidestepped the issue by
appealing to commonsensical living. This
provided, however, neither a theoretical basis for beliefs nor a
refutation of the arguments that questioned them.
Kant saw that Hume had posed a most fundamental challenge to all human
knowledge claims. To answer
him, it had to be shown not that knowledge is possible but how it is
possible. Kant combined a Skepticism
toward metaphysical knowledge with the contention that certain universal
and necessary conditions are involved
in having experience and describing it. In terms of these it is possible
to have genuine knowledge about the forms
of all possible experience, space and time, and about the categories in
which all experience is described. Any
effort to apply this beyond all possible experience, however, leads into
contradictions and Skepticism. It is not
possible to know about things-in-themselves nor about the causes of
experience.
Though Kant thought that he had resolved the Skeptical problems, some of
his contemporaries saw his
philosophy as commencing a new Skeptical era. G.E. Schulze (or
Schulze-Aenesidemus) a notable critic
of Kantianism, insisted that, on Kant's theory, no one could know any
objective truths about anything; he could
only know the subjective necessity of his views. The Jewish critic
Salomon Maimon contended that,
though there are such things as a priori concepts, their application to
experience is always problematical, and
whether they apply can only be found through experience. Hence, the
possibility of knowledge can never be
established with certainty. Assured truth on the basis of concepts is
possible only of human creations, like
mathematical ideas, and it is questionable whether these have any
objective truth. The thesis that human creativity
is the basis of truth, however, was soon to be developed by Johann G.
Fichte, a leading German Idealist,
as a new way of transcending Skepticism.
Another Skeptical critic of Kant, J.G. Hamann, saw in Hume's and Kant's
work a new basis for fideism.
If knowledge of reality cannot be gained by rational means, t