V--The Ethics of Elfland
WHEN the business man rebukes the idealism of his office-boy, it is
commonly in some such speech as this: "Ah, yes, when one is young,
one has these ideals in the abstract and these castles in the air; but in
middle age they all break up like clouds, and one comes down to a belief
in practical politics, to using the machinery one has and getting on with
the world as it is." Thus, at least, venerable and philanthropic old men
now in their honoured graves used to talk to me when I was a boy. But
since then I have grown up and have discovered that these philanthropicold men were telling lies. What has really happened is exactly theopposite of what they said would happen. They said that I should losemy ideals and begin to believe in the methods of practical politicians.Now, I have not lost my ideals in the least; my faith in fundamentals isexactly what it always was. What I have lost is my old childlike faith inpractical politics. I am still as much concerned as ever about the Battle ofArmageddo n; but I am not so much concerned about the GeneralElection. As a babe I leapt up on my mother's knee at themere mentionof it. No; the vision is always solid and reliable. The vision is always afact. It is the reality that is often a fraud. As much as I e ver did, morethan I ever did, I believe in Liberalism. But there was a rosy time ofinnocence when I believed in Liberals.
I take this instance of one of the enduring faiths because, having now totrace the roots of my personal speculation, this may be counted, I think,as the only positive bias. I was brought up a Liberal, and have alwaysbelieved in democracy, in the elemen tary liberal doctrine of a
self-governing humanity. If any one finds the phrase vague or
threadbare, I can only pause for a moment to explain that the principle ofdemocracy, as I mean it, can be stated in two propositions. The first isthis: that the things common to all men are more important than the
things peculiar to any men. Ordinary things are more valuable than
extraordinary things; nay, they are more extraordinary. Man is
something more awful than men; something more strange. The sense of
the miracle of humanity itself should be always more vivid to us than
any marvels of power, intellect, art, or civilization. The mere man on
two legs, as such, should be felt as something more heartbreaking than
any music and more startling than any caricature. Death is more tragic
even than death by starvation. Having a nose is more comic even than
having a Norman nose.
This is the first principle of democracy: that the essential things in men
are the things they hold in common, not the things they hold separately.
And the second principle is merely this: that the political instinct or
desire is one of these things which they hold in common. Falling in love
is more poetical than dropping into poetry. The democratic contention is
that government (helping to rule the tribe) is a thing like falling in love,
and not a thing like dropping into poetry. It is not something analogous
to playing the church organ, painting on vellum, discovering the North
Pole (that insidious habit), looping the loop, being Astronomer Royal,
and so on. For these things we do not wish a man to do at all unless he
does them well. It is, on the contrary, a thing analogous to writing one's
own love-letters or blowing one's own nose. These things we want a
man to do for himself, even if he does them badly. I am not here arguing the truth of any of these conceptions; I know that some moderns areasking to have their wives chosen by scientists, and they may soon beasking, for all I know, to have their noses blown by nurses. I merelysay that mankind does recognize these universal human functions, andthat democracy classes government among them. In short, thedemocratic faith is this: that the most terribly important things must beleft to ordinary men themselv es -- the mating of the sexes, the rearing ofthe young, the laws of the state. This is democracy; and in this I havealways believed.
But there is one thing that I have never from my youth up been able to
understand. I have never been able to understand where people got the
idea that democracy was in some way opposed to tradition. It is obviousthat tradition is only democracy extended through time. It is trusting to aconsensus of common human voices rather than to some isolated orarbitrary record. The man who quotes some German historian againstthe tradition of the Catholic Church, for instance, is strictly appealing toaristocracy. He is appealing to the superiority of one expert against the awful authority of a mob. It is quite easy to see why a legend is treated,and oug ht to be treated, more respectfully than a book of history. Thelegend is generally made by the majority of people in the village, whoare sane. The book is generally written by the one man in the villagewho is mad. Those who urge against tradition that men in the past wereignorant may go and urge it at the Carlton Club, along with the statementthat voters in the slums are ignorant. It will not do for us. If we attachgreat importance to the opinion of ordinary men in great unanimity whenwe are dealing with daily matters, there is no reason why we shoulddisregard it when we are dealing with history or fable. Tradition may bedefined as an extension of the franchise. Tradition means giving votes to the most obscure of all classes, our ancestors. It is the demo cracy of thedead. Tradition refuses to submit to the small and arrogant oligarchy ofthose who merely happen to be walking about. All democrats object to
men being disqualified by the accident of birth; tradition objects to theirbeing disqualified by the accident of death. Democracy tells us not toneglect a good man's opinion, even if he is our groom; tradition asks us not to neglect a good man's opinio n, even if he is our father. I, at any
rate, cannot separate the two ideas of democracy and tradition; it seemsevident to me that they are the same idea. We will have the dead at ourcouncils. The ancient Greeks voted by stones; these shall vote by
tombstones. It is all quite regular and official, for most tombstones, likemost ballot papers, are marked with a cross.
I have first to say, therefore, that if I have had a bias, it was always a
bias in favour of democracy, and therefore of tradition. Before we come
to any theoretic or logical beginnings I am content to allow for that
personal equation; I have always been more inclined to believe the ruck
of hard-working people than to believe that special and troublesome
literary class to which I belong. I prefer even the fancies and prejudicesof the people who see life from the inside to the clearest demonstrations of the people who see life from the outside. I would always trust the oldwives' fables against the old m aids' facts. As long as wit is mother wit it can be as wild as it pleases.
Now, I have to put together a general position, and I pretend to no
training in such things. I propose to do it, therefore, by writing down
one after another the three or four fundamental ideas which I have foundfor myself, pretty much in the way that I found them. Then I shall
roughly synthesise them, summing up my personal philosophy or
natural religion; then shall describe my startling discovery that the wholething had been discovered before. It had been discovered by
Christianity. But of these profound persuasions which I have to recount
in order, the earliest was concerned with this element of popular
tradition. And without the foregoing explanation touching tradition and
democracy I could hardly make my mental experience clear. As it is, I
do not know whether I can make it clear, but I now propose to try.
My first and last philosophy, that which I believe in with unbroken
certainty, I learnt in the nursery. I generally learnt it from a nurse; that
is, from the solemn and star-appointed priestess at once of democracy
and tradition. The things I believed most then, the things I believe most
now, are the things called fairy tales. They seem to me to be the entirelyreasonable things. They are not fantasies: compared with them other things are fantastic. Compared with them religion and rationalism are
both abnormal, though religion is abnormally right and rationalism
abnormally wrong. Fairyland is nothing but the sunny country of
common sense. It is not earth that judges heaven, but heaven that judges earth; so for me at least it was not earth that criticised elfland, but elflandthat criticised the earth. I knew the magic beanstalk before I had tastedbeans; I was sure of the Ma n in the Moon before I was certain of the moon. This was at one with all popular tradition. Modern minor poets are naturalists, and talk about the bush or the brook; but the singers of the old epics and fables were supernaturalists, and talked about the g odsof brook and bush. That is what the moderns mean when they say thatthe ancients did not "appreciate Nature," because they said that Naturewas divine. Old nurses do not tell children about the grass, but about thefairies that dance on the grass; and the old Greeks could not see the treesfor the dryads.
But I deal here with what ethic and philosophy come from being fed on
fairy tales. If I were describing them in detail I could note many noble
and healthy principles that arise from them. There is the chivalrous
lesson of "Jack the Giant Killer"; that giants should be killed because
they are gigantic. It is a manly mutiny against pride as such. For the
rebel is older than all the kingdoms, and the Jacobin has more tradition
than the Jacobite. There is the lesson of "Cinderella," which is the same
as that of the Magnificat -- exaltavit humiles. There is the great lesson of "Beauty and the Beast"; that a thing must be loved before it is loveable. The human creature was blessed with all birthday gifts, yet cursed with death; and how death also may perhaps be softened to a sleep. But I am not concerned with any of the separate statutes of elfand, but with the whole spirit of its law, which I learnt before I could speak, and shall retain when I cannot write. I am concerned with a certain way of look ing at life, which was created in me by the fairy tales, but has since beenmeekly ratified by the mere facts.
It might be stated this way. There are certain sequences or developments
(cases of one thing following another), which are, in the true sense of
the word, reasonable. They are, in the true sense of the word,
necessary. Such are mathematical and merely logical sequences. We in
fairyland (who are the most reasonable of all creatures) admit that reason
and that necessity. For instance, if the Ugly Sisters are older than
Cinderella, it is (in an iron and awful sense) necessary that Cinderella is
younger than the Ugly Sisters. There is no getting out of it. Haeckel
may talk as much fatalism about that fact as he pleases: it really must be.
If Jack is the son of a miller, a miller is the father of Jack. Cold reason
decrees it from her awful throne: and we in fairyland submit. If the three
brothers all ride horses, there are six animals and eighteen legs involved:
that is true rationalism, and fairyland is full of it. But as I put my head
over the hedge of the elves and began to take notice of the natural world,
I observed an extraordinary thing. I observed that learned men in
spectacles were talking of the actual things that happened -- dawn and
death and so on -- as if they were rational and inevitable. They talked as
if the fact that trees bear fruit were just as necessary as the fact that two
and one trees make three. But it is not. There is an enormous difference
by the test of fairyland; which is the test of the imagination. You cannot
imagine two and one not making three. But you can easily imagine trees
not growing fruit; you can imagine them growing golden candlesticks or
tigers hanging on by the tail. These men in spectacles spoke much of a
man named Newton, who was hit by an apple, and who discovered a
law. But they could not be got to see the distinction between a true law,
a law of reason, and the mere fact of apples falling. If the apple hit
Newton's nose, Newton's nose hit the apple. That is a true necessity:
because we cannot conceive the one occurring without the other. But we
can quite well conceive the apple not falling on his nose; we can fancy it
flying ardently through the air to hit some other nose, of which it had a
more definite dislike. We have always in our fairy tales kept this sharp
distinction between the science of mental relations, in which there really
are laws, and the science of physical facts, in which there are no laws,
but only weird repetitions. We believe in bodily miracles, but not in
mental impossibilities. We believe that a Bean-stalk climbed up to
Heaven; but that does not at all confuse our convictions on the
philosophical question of how many beans make five.
Here is the peculiar perfection of tone and truth in the nursery tales. The
man of science says, "Cut the stalk, and the apple will fall"; but he says
it calmly, as if the one idea really led up to the other. The witch in the
fairy tale says, "Blow the horn, and the ogre's castle will fall"; but she
does not say it as if it were something in which the effect obviously
arose out of the cause. Doubtless she has given the advice to many
champions, and has seen many castles fall, but she does not lose either
her wonder or her reason. She does not muddle her head until it
imagines a necessary mental connection between a horn and a falling
tower. But the scientific men do muddle their heads, until they imagine a
necessary mental connection between an apple leaving the tree and an
apple reaching the ground. They do really talk as if they had found not
only a set of marvellous facts, but a truth connecting those facts. They
do talk as if the connection of two strange things physically connected
them philosophically. They feel that because one incomprehensible thing
constantly follows another incomprehensible thing the two together
somehow make up a comprehensible thing. Two black riddles make a
white answer.
In fairyland we avoid the word "law"; but in the land of science they are
singularly fond of it. Thus they will call some interesting conjecture
about how forgotten folks pronounced the alphabet, Grimm's Law. But
Grimm's Law is far less intellectual than Grimm's Fairy Tales. The tales
are, at any rate, certainly tales; while the law is not a law. A law implies
that we know the nature of the generalisation and enactment; not merely
that we have noticed some of the effects. If there is a law that
pick-pockets shall go to prison, it implies that there is an imaginable
mental connection between the idea of prison and the idea of picking
pockets. And we know what the idea is. We can say why we take liberty
from a man who takes liberties. But we cannot say why an egg can turn
into a chicken any more than we can say why a bear could turn into a
fairy prince. As ideas, the egg and the chicken are further off from each
other than the bear and the prince; for no egg in itself suggests a
chicken, whereas some princes do suggest bears. Granted, then, that
certain transformations do happen, it is essential that we should regard
them in the philosophic manner of fairy tales, not in the unphilosophic
manner of science and the "Laws of Nature." When we are asked why
eggs turn to birds or fruits fall in autumn, we must answer exactly as the
fairy godmother would answer if Cinderella asked her why mice turned
to horses or her clothes fell from her at twelve o'clock. We must answer
that it is magic. It is not a "law," for we do not understand its general
formula. It is not a necessity, for though we can count on it happening
practically, we have no right to say that it must always happen. It is no
argument for unalterable law (as Huxley fancied) that we count on the
ordinary course of things. We do not count on it; we bet on it. We risk
the remote possibility of a miracle as we do that of a poisoned pancake
or a world-destroying comet. We leave it out of account, not because it
is a miracle, and therefore an impossibility, but because it is a miracle,
and therefore an exception. All the terms used in the science books,
"law," "necessity," "order," "tendency," and so on, are really
unintellectual, because they assume an inner synthesis, which we do not
possess. The only words that ever satisfied me as describing Nature are
the terms used in the fairy books, "charm," "spell," "enchantment."
They express the arbitrariness of the fact and its mystery. A tree grows
fruit because it is a magic tree. Water runs downhill because it is
bewitched. The sun shines because it is bewitched.
I deny altogether that this is fantastic or even mystical. We may have
some mysticism later on; but this fairy-tale language about things is
simply rational and agnostic. It is the only way I can express in words
my clear and definite perception that one thing is quite distinct from
another; that there is no logical connection between flying and laying
eggs. It is the man who talks about "a law" that he has never seen who
is the mystic. Nay, the ordinary scientific man is strictly a sentimentalist.
He is a sentimentalist in this essential sense, that he is soaked and swept
away by mere associations. He has so often seen birds fly and lay eggs
that he feels as if there must be some dreamy, tender connection between
the two ideas, whereas there is none. A forlorn lover might be unable to
dissociate the moon from lost love; so the materialist is unable to
dissociate the moon from the tide. In both cases there is no connection,
except that one has seen them together. A sentimentalist might shed tears
at the smell of apple-blossom, because, by a dark association of his
own, it reminded him of his boyhood. So the materialist professor
(though he conceals his tears) is yet a sentimentalist, because, by a dark
association of his own, apple-blossoms remind him of apples. But the
cool rationalist from fairyland does not see why, in the abstract, the
apple tree should not grow crimson tulips; it sometimes does in his
country.
This elementary wonder, however, is not a mere fancy derived from the
fairy tales; on the contrary, all the fire of the fairy tales is derived from
this. Just as we all like love tales because there is an instinct of sex, we
all like astonishing tales because they touch the nerve of the ancient
instinct of astonishment. This is proved by the fact that when we are
very young children we do not need fairy tales: we only need tales. Mere
life is interesting enough. A child of seven is excited by being told that
Tommy opened a door and saw a dragon. But a child of three is excited
by being told that Tommy opened a door. Boys like romantic tales; but
babies like realistic tales -- because they find them romantic. In fact, a
baby is about the only person, I should think, to whom a modern
realistic novel could be read without boring him. This proves that even
nursery tales only echo an almost pre-natal leap of interest and
amazement. These tales say that apples were golden only to refresh the
forgotten moment when we found that they were green. They make
rivers run with wine only to make us remember, for one wild moment,
that they run with water. I have said that this is wholly reasonable and
even agnostic. And, indeed, on this point I am all for the higher
agnosticism; its better name is Ignorance. We have all read in scientific
books, and, indeed, in all romances, the story of the man who has
forgotten his name. This man walks about the streets and can see and
appreciate everything; only he cannot remember who he is. Well, every
man is that man in the story. Every man has forgotten who he is. One
may understand the cosmos, but never the ego; the self more distant than
any star. Thou shalt love the Lord thy God; but thou shalt not know
thyself. We are all under the same mental calamity; we have all forgotten
our names. We have all forgotten what we really are. All that we call
common sense and rationality and practicality and positivism only means
that for certain dead levels of our life we forget that we have forgotten.
All that we call spirit and art and ecstacy only means that for one awful
instant we remember that we forget.
But though (like the man without memory in the novel) we walk the
streets with a sort of half-witted admiration, still it is admiration. It is
admiration in English and not only admiration in Latin. The wonder has
a positive element of praise. This is the next milestone to be definitely
marked on our road through fairyland. I shall speak in the next chapter
about optimists and pessimists in their intellectual aspect, so far as they
have one. Here am only trying to describe the enormous emotions which
cannot be described. And the strongest emotion was that life was as
precious as it was puzzling. It was an ecstacy because it was an
adventure; it was an adventure because it was an opportunity. The
goodness of the fairy tale was not affected by the fact that there might be
more dragons than princesses; it was good to be in a fairy tale. The test
of all happiness is gratitude; and I felt grateful, though I hardly knew to
whom. Children are grateful when Santa Claus puts in their stockings
gifts of toys or sweets. Could I not be grateful to Santa Claus when he
put in my stockings the gift of two miraculous legs? We thank people
for birthday presents of cigars and slippers. Can I thank no one for the
birthday present of birth?
There were, then, these two first feelings, indefensible and indisputable.
The world was a shock, but it was not merely shocking; existence was a
surprise, but it was a pleasant surprise. In fact, all my first views were
exactly uttered in a riddle that stuck in my brain from boyhood. The
question was, "What did the first frog say?" And the answer was,
"Lord, how you made me jump!" That says succinctly all that I am
saying. God made the frog jump; but the frog prefers jumping. But
when these things are settled there enters the second great principle of
the fairy philosophy.
Any one can see it who will simply read "Grimm's Fairy Tales" or the
fine collections of Mr. Andrew Lang. For the pleasure of pedantry I will
call it the Doctrine of Conditional Joy. Touchstone talked of much virtue
in an "if"; according to elfin ethics all virtue is in an "if." The note of the
fairy utterance always is, "You may live in a palace of gold and
sapphire, if you do not say the word `cow"'; or "You may live happily
with the King's daughter, if you do not show her an onion." The vision
always hangs upon a veto. All the dizzy and colossal things conceded
depend upon one small thing withheld. All the wild and whirling things
that are let loose depend upon one thing that is forbidden. Mr. W. B.
Yeats, in his exquisite and piercing elfin poetry, describes the elves as
lawless; they plunge in innocent anarchy on the unbridled horses of the
air --
"Ride on the crest of the dishevelled tide, And dance
upon the mountains like a flame."